Diagnostic Reasoning

 

Clinical decision making is the process by which we determine who needs what and when. While not exactly arbitrary, this exercise can be quite subjective. Each provider compiles their own data (hence the emphasis on learning to perform an accurate H&P) and then constructs an argument for a particular disease state based on their interpretation of the “facts.” The strength of their case will depend on the way in which they gather and assemble information. There may then be no single, right way of applying diagnostic and therapeutic strategies to a particular case. Medicine involves playing the odds, assessing the relative chance that a patient is/is not suffering from a particular illness. Codifying the way in which providers logically approach problems and deal with this uncertainty is a difficult task. Relying solely on the classic features of a disease may be misleading. That is because the clinical presentation of a disease often varies: the symptoms and signs of many conditions are non-specific initially and may require hours, days, or even months to develop.

Generating a differential diagnosis; that is, developing a list of the possible conditions that might produce a patient’s symptoms and signs, is an important part of clinical reasoning. It enables appropriate testing to rule out possibilities and confirm a final diagnosis.

This case portrays a poor patient outcome after a misdiagnosis.

Case scenario

A previously healthy 35-year-old lawyer presents to a primary care office with a chief complaint of chest pain and a non-productive cough. The pain started suddenly two hours prior to coming to the office while the patient was sitting at his desk. The patient describes the pain as sharp in nature, constantly present but made worse with inspiration and movement, and with radiation to the base of the neck. His blood pressure in the right arm and other vital signs are normal

On physical examination, the only findings of note are chest wall tenderness and a faint cardiac murmur. The ECG in the office is normal. The patient is observed for an hour in the office and assessed. He is diagnosed with viral pleurisy and sent home on non-steroidal analgesics.

The following day the patient collapses at home and cannot be resuscitated by the paramedic service. An autopsy reveals a Type 1 aortic dissection with pericardial tamponade.

Discussion Assignment:

Developing a list of possible conditions that might produce a patient’s symptoms and signs is an important part of clinical reasoning.

As an NP in primary care, what would you have done differently?

Discuss the importance of creating a list of differentials for this patient. How could it have changed this outcome?

If a serious diagnosis comes to mind based on a patient’s symptoms:

Ask yourself: Have you considered the likelihood of a serious diagnosis and whether it needs to be ruled out by testing or referral?
Because many serious disorders are challenging to diagnose, have you considered ruling out the worst-case scenario?
Ask yourself: Do you have a sufficient understanding of the clinical presentation to offer an opinion on the diagnosis?
What other diagnoses could it be? How might the treatment to date have altered the patient’s outcome?
What other diagnostic and laboratory or imaging was needed in order to make a complete differential list? What support tools would you consider using in helping to create a differential diagnosis list?
Are you familiar with the current clinical practice guidelines for the investigation of a suspected condition such as chest pain?

 

Sample Solution

A dynamic thought process known as diagnostic reasoning results in the discovery of the hypothesis that best explains the clinical evidence. Modern advanced practice nurses typically determine the cause of medical and nursing issues that arise in seriously unwell and acutely ill individuals. Unique elements that can impact the standard of diagnostic reasoning and perhaps make the process more challenging are inherent in the speciality sectors of acute and critical care. Clinicians and students who want to develop their diagnostic abilities must have a solid grasp of the fundamental ideas that guide diagnostic reasoning as well as the associated typical mistakes.

ever consistently (Begby et al (2006b), Page 326-31). This is upheld by Frowe, who estimates the genuine strategies as per proportionality and military need. It relies upon the size of how much harm done to each other, to pass judgment on the activities after a conflict. For instance, one can’t just nuke the psychological militant gatherings all through the center east, since it isn’t just relative, it will harm the entire populace, an unseen side-effect. All the more critically, the troopers should have the right expectation in the thing they will accomplish, forfeiting the expenses for their activities. For instance: if fighters have any desire to execute all detainees of war, they should do it for the right goal and for a noble motivation, corresponding to the damage done to them. This is upheld by Vittola: ‘not generally legal to execute all warriors… we should consider… size of the injury caused by the foe.’ This is additionally upheld by Frowe approach, which is much more upright than Vittola’s view however infers similar plans: ‘can’t be rebuffed essentially for battling.’ This implies one can’t just rebuff another on the grounds that they have been a soldier. They should be treated as compassionately as could be expected. Be that as it may, the circumstance is heightened in the event that killing them can prompt harmony and security, inside the interests, everything being equal. By and large, jus in bello proposes in wars, mischief must be utilized against warriors, never against the blameless. In any case, eventually, the point is to lay out harmony and security inside the republic. As Vittola’s decision: ‘the quest for equity for which he battles and the safeguard of his country’ is the thing countries ought to be battling for in wars (Begby et al (2006b), Page 332). In this way, albeit the present world has created, we can see not vastly different from the pioneer accounts on fighting and the traditionists, giving one more segment of the hypothesis of the simply war. By the by, we can in any case presume that there can’t be one authoritative hypothesis of the simply war hypothesis in view of its normativity.

Jus post bellum
At last, jus post bellum proposes that the moves we ought to initiate after a conflict (Frowe (2010), Page 208). Vittola, right off the bat, contends after a conflict, it is the obligation of the pioneer to judge how to manage the foe (Begby et al (2006b), Page 332).. Once more, proportionality is underscored. For instance, the Versailles deal forced after the First World War is tentatively excessively cruel, as it was not all Germany’s problem for the conflict. This is upheld by Frowe, who communicates two perspectives in jus post bellum: Minimalism and Maximalism, which are very contrasting perspectives. Minimalists propose a more tolerant methodology while maximalist, supporting the above model, gives a crueler methodology, rebuffing the foe both financially and strategically (Frowe (2010), Page 208). At the last occasion, nonetheless, the point of war is to lay out harmony security, so whatever should be done can be ethically legitimate, assuming that it observes the guidelines of jus promotion bellum. All in all, simply war hypothesis is truly contestable and can contend in various ways. Nonetheless, the foundation of a fair harmony is pivotal, making all war type circumstance to have various approaches to drawing nearer (Frowe (2010), Page 227). In any case, the simply war hypothesis contains jus promotion bellum, jus in bello and jus post bellum, and I

This question has been answered.

Get Answer
WeCreativez WhatsApp Support
Our customer support team is here to answer your questions. Ask us anything!
👋 Hi, Welcome to Compliant Papers.